Prof., Dr. Vladimir Katasonov
(Moscow)
Fragile balance of culture:
We discern in human culture three main spheres of cognition: science, philosophy, religion (not to say especially about art). The first two form a domain of our activity. In religion man is more receptive. So, science and philosophy express together one stream in culture, religion does the second one. Let’s discuss these spheres more thoroughly.
Saying about modern science we
mean the so called exact sciences, having precision and measurement as their
characteristic features. Science gives mathematical description of fragments of
reality to be checked then in experiment. “To check in experiment” means that
we compare the values of parameters pre–dicted
by a theory with the values obtained
in experiment. “Obtain values in experiment” means we have to measure
them. Natural sciences are unthinkable without measurement. This is a
characteristic feature of modern science. In Galileo’s works[1]
we see how insistently he seeks to find a connection of parameters (e.g. in the
law of movement). This connection is always a function. It is
interesting that in mathematics they give the definition of function and begin
to study them systematically in XVII century as well[2],
in the time of emergence of modern science. This calculus of functions –
Differential and Integral Calculus – becomes main theoretical tool of new
science.
The seeking of mathematical exactitude
depends on the tie of modern science with technics. Modern science, the one of
Galileo, Descartes, Huygens, emerged both in heads of philosophers and mathematicians and in
mechanical workshops. To build a machine it is necessary to know exact
dimensions. To make a gear, launch an artificial satellite, make a chemical
reaction to run in the right direction, one has to know to calculate exactly
them. Scientific synthesis is always a concordance of quantities. So, a truth
of thing and its determination are sought by science as a determination
of quantity. Reduction of all the variety of experience to quantity was one
of the main task of modern science from the very beginning. Pioneers of XVII
century’s science tried to resolve this problem by different ways. Thanks his
metaphysics Descartes reduces physics to geometry and the last, by the method
of analytical geometry to arithmetic, i.e. to calculations. Galileo tried by
his sophisticated dialectics to refute Plato’s thesis about matter’s inability
to embody exact geometrical forms. In his turn, Leibniz’ phenomenological
rethinking of space and time helped substantially to the progress of
mathematical physics. The parallel development of new branches of mathematics –
theory of differential equations, theory of complex functions, etc. - more and
more strengthens authority of mathematical science and gradually accustoms to
see in it a paradigm of science in general. “In every learning about nature
there is as much science in strict sense as it has mathematics” (I.Kant)[3].
Physical science of Antiquity and
Middle Ages was of other kind. Measurement and qualitative characteristics were
not main method and task of cognition. Science of Antiquity considered that one
can measure only that what can embody exact mathematical forms. This was valid
only for so called “supralunar sphere” of fifth element (“quinta essentia” of Aristotle) and, generally
speaking, for astronomy, laws of motion of celestial bodies. But “sublunar
world”, terrestrial things in particular, was in principle indescribable in the
language of mathematics. Just because matter can’t exactly embody ideal
forms. So Aristotle’s physics has
qualitative language. To understand a movement here means to interpret
it in terms of Aristotle’s four causes: formal, material, efficient and final
ones. Physics of Aristotle considered movement, so to say, “in its genetic
wholeness”, in its tie with the whole order of Cosmos. The modern science is
interested more by process of movement, its phenomenal side, its parts,
including infinitesimal ones and this is studied by quantitative methods.
Notwithstanding the metaphysical pathos of modern science’s fathers – Galileo,
Descartes, Leibniz, Newton – ontological questions gradually moved away in the
background. History of science shows a play of different scientific paradigms –
atomism, ether, energitism – but none can pretend to express the deepest level
of reality. Science doesn’t reach the ultimate reality. That what science
really can is more or less reliable mathematical description of human experience. This “more or less” is a
matter of principle. In spite of pathos of exactitude in exact sciences
we, strictly speaking, can say definitely about no scientific theory whether it
is true or not. Experimental justification of a scientific theory gives closeness
of the predicted values to ones of experiment only in the limits of error of
experiment. It means two different scientific theories giving predictions
that differ from experimental results not more than experiment’s error, are not
discernable by our method. But these theories can give good approximations of
experimental data for the space and time acheavable for us and, at the same
time, completely different values for the great time and space. Because that it
is not logically correct to deduce from “justified” scientific theories any
ontological statements or just long – term predictions (e.g., like theory of
the so called “heat death” of Universe, so hotly discussed on the border of XIX
– XX centuries). Paradoxically, the program to obtain an exact quantitative
description in exact sciences has its boundary in the scientific method itself.
Modern science had the difficulties to
realize the program “to give exact mathematical description to all the
existing” in notion of number
itself, too. Science (and philosophy) of Antiquity saying “number” means only
integer. Greek science uses intensively the notion of the ratio of integers, as
well, but nowise considers it as a number (as we do today using rational
numbers). Having discovered the fact of incommensurability, e.g. of a
square’s diagonal with its side, Greeks refused Pythagoras’ ideology “all is a
number” or, in more liberal form, “all can be measured”. There is an
incommensurability in the world, a continuous value, continuum can’t be as a whole
described through numerical correlations. So science of Antiquity approved the dualistic
paradigm as a philosophical base of its
considerations: side by side with the measurable, there is an other
principle in the world, the ir – rational… But modern science pretends to
measure all and with any precision. Is it possible however ? To discuss this
one needs more fundamental language than
a scientific one, namely philosophical language.
Immediately philosophy wants to put in
order our cognition, elucidate and define what do we mean saying: I know, it’s
evident, it’s proved, it’s possible (or not) etc. Deepening the discussion
about scientific knowledge we come naturally to philosophy. Thus, we say about
measurement as a characteristic feature of modern science. But what does it
mean “to measure” ? What does exactly mean “size of a thing” ? What is a
“boundary of a thing” ? Measurement turn out to be a deep philosophical problem
touching fundamental questions. Not to “get stuck” in these questions science
has to respond to them more or less conditionally and conventionally. In
philosophy one meets these questions “face to face”. Most of them has no final
response, nevertheless philosophy teaches us two things: 1) not to accept wrong
responses for the true ones, resist to the “idols of truth”; 2) to state the
value, in a sense, of the epistemological depth of the problem to resolve.
To begin discussion about measurement
better may be from the question: Is really all measurable ? Can one measure
freedom, beauty, love ? We say: “He loves her so much”. Does really one means
here a qualitative aspect ? Could we really compensate by money the “moral
damage” ? All these questions are very complicated ones. It is important to
stress that they interpret most of the measurements used in natural sciences,
e.g. measurements of colour, heat, brightness etc. in no natural sense, but
quite the contrary, in very conditional one, that demands special philosophical
theories. Usually it’s theory dividing things qualities on two parts: primary
(space, form, movement) and secondary ones (colour, temperature, taste, smell
etc.) and a reduction of the latter to the former. The question about the
validity of this theory, being discussed from XVII century, is very complicated
one not only for physics, physiology, psychology but for philosophy as well.
What do we measure, hence, depends on what a physical, - and metaphysical ! –
hypothesis have we accepted. Nature is describable from different points of
view, complementary one to another, and a possible completeness of its
description is always an unattainable ideal of science…
The question “What do we measure ?”
has another philosophical side. What do we really have in our experience:
either a result of interaction of things with our organs of perceptions
(reinforced by experimental technics) i.e. phenomena, or reality
itself of things, i.e. things as they exist in themselves. What do we
really cognize ? In history of philosophy both points of view were deeply
elaborated. If we adopt that only phenomena are given, it raises many new
questions: What is this “phenomenological space” where features of things are
presented ? What it depends on ? How is possible, then, the thought about
“thing itself” ? Thus Leibniz’, Kant’s, Husserl’s philosophical systems emerge.
If otherwise we adopt that reality itself is given us in experiment then other
questions arise: What is the human ability to touch that ‘what really is” ?
What is a character of that reality ? What is our place in it ? Responses may
be rather different. Thus, Plato taught that true reality is a “world of ideas”
and things are only imperfect embodiment of those. For Aristotle an essence
of thing is this concrete thing, as a definite unity of form and matter.
Modernity gives its own responses on this question. For Descartes all existing
can be reduced to two essences: res extensa and res cogitans. All
the nature, except man, should be reduced with help of mathematics,
practically, to geometrical constructions. For Leibniz all Universum consists
out of monads, ideal principles, having perceptions and will. In accordance
with what kind of metaphysics we adopt, we’ll interpret differently our
cognition and science.
There is one more philosophical topic
growing necessarily from discussions about measurement. I told that Antiquity’s
science recognized as a number only integers. We added to them rational and
irrational numbers. So for us, contrary to Greek mathematics, every segment can
be measured by a unit of length. They used this considerations already from
XVII century but it’s curious that strict theory of real numbers was
build only by the end of XIX century (Dedekind, Weierstrass, Cantor). It is
significant that these theories use substantially actual infinity. But
long time ago the question of principle was put: Is it logically correct to use
actual infinity ? All our experience is finite and much more: Greek science
already understood that using of actual infinity implicates unsolvable
contradictions, aporia (famous Zeno’s paradoxes: the Dichotomy, the
Achilles, the Arrow). In mathematical theory of actual infinite sets ( the sets
theory), built by the end of XIX century, similar paradoxes and aporia were
found as well (Russel’s paradox, the notion “set of all the sets”, discussions
concerning the axiom of choice etc.) The opponents of actual infinity told: we
can’t imagine infinity, we have no right to use it in science. The proponents
argued: we can’t imaging many things, e.g. big numbers, “thousand”, “million”,
but as a matter of fact yet they exist… Also an actual infinity exists:
without any doubt, you know, God, an Infinite Reason sees all the infinite
set of numbers as a whole. This curious argument for justification of his
theory of infinity G.Cantor used too, quoting St.Augustine[4].
It is significant that science in its development comes to necessity to see
things sub specie aeternitatis, from God’s point of view. This is not
yet “God of Abraham, Isaac and Jacob”, but only “God of philosophers and
scientists”, World Reason, Logos, ruling the world, a completeness of all the
natural laws. Notwithstanding that scientist doesn’t need “a hypothesis of God”
it is important that seeking a completeness of logical conditions[5]
of scientific knowledge, he comes to questions: “What is an essence of the Law
ruling the world?” and “Does a Law – giver exist ?” We see that our knowledge
in science and philosophy depends of our world – outlook orientation, expressed
either in some regulative principles or rightly in theology. The last is a base
of data’s interpretations and just through this base religion and worldoutlook
influence science. Not only our understanding of nature, but our perception
of it and, hence, sense of art depend on our worldoutlook orientation, too.
Generally speaking philosophy seeks to
see a sense of cognition more strictly. This strictness of thought is a
striving to represent every object of thought against a background of
infinitely different opportunities of the other, the strictly outlined
“logical contour” of this object to appear in all its definiteness and
specificity. These two features contain a kind of canon for philosophy: to seek
for strictness of definition and, at the same time, to understand all the
boundlessness of the possible. Philosophy remains always “in the middle”:
knowing neither its origins nor its ends… As if philosophy follows Pascal’s
maxim: “The greatness of man is in keeping to the middle”[6].
Not all in culture and life is
confined to the “daylight consciousness”. Science and philosophy are only
islands of the more or less understandable, rationalized in boundless ocean of
life. There are places in life for the miraculous, dark, for miracle… There is
a sphere of the mystic: surmises, concurrences,
illuminations,
missings… It is very difficult to
rationalize them. The mystic has a characteristic feature differing it from
science and philosophy. The latter necessary “work” in the situation of a logical
boundary between subject and object, the cognizing principle (organ, ability,
method) and ob – jectum being
cognized. Mysticism says insistently about overcoming of subject – object
division, about “direct entry” in object…
There are different kinds of mysticism:
aesthetic, hedonistic, intellectual, social, national… Christian mysticism is
characterized by an experience of brotherhood with the others in Christ, when
Christians feel themselves as members of mystical Christ Body, His Church. From
all the sphere of the mystical religion is distinguished by two
characteristic features:
1. The Irrational, superrational God, the completeness of
Wisdom, Power and Holiness appears as a Person, the personal meeting with God
occurs;
2. God reveal us Himself, the meeting with God is
an event to decide by God. We can only search after God, strive for this
personal meeting, but the result depends, at the end, on God’s will only. Jesus
Christ says to his apostles: “You didn’t choose me, but I chose you and appointed
you that you should go and bear fruit and that your fruit should
abide…”(Jn.15:16). Science and philosophy are human reason attempts to
interpret reality. Activity is here on the side of man. In religion activity is
on the side of Godhead. Certainly our understanding of revelation depends on
our expectations, our scientific, philosophical and cultural vocabulary: our
theology is influenced by our understanding of world. But nevertheless,
activity in religion is on God’s side: if He needs, God can make “the very
stones would cry out” (Lk.19:40).
Reality that is higher than human one is
revealed us in religious experience… Man’s part here is a humble searching of
this revelation. Humility turns out to be a necessary point of
intercourse with God, with the Sacred: “Then He said [to Moses from the burning
bush], “Do not come near; put off your shoes from your feet, for the place on
which you are standing is holy ground” (Ex.3:5). “God opposes to the proud, but
gives grace to the humble” (Jas.4:6), teaches us the Holy Scripture. Humility
of man’s heart, crying for his sins is a genuine sacrifice to God: “The
sacrifice acceptable to God is a broken spirit; a broken and contrite heart, o
God, thou wilt not despise” (Ps.51, 17). Having been vocated to be God’s
children, Christians should in their faith and gentleness be spiritually like
children, too: “Truly, I say to you, unless you turn and become like children,
you will never enter the kindom of heaven” (Mt.18:3).
There is a characteristic distinction
between religion and science and philosophy. The latter are always some theories,
as a logical (or mathematical) schemes of reality. Religion in its
kernel is a reality itself ! Not only the reality enlightened,
participating to sense, but the one identical with sense. Not just
reality – in – itself, but the one giving sense and being, enlightening and
blessing to all in the world – the Sacred. Religion in this sense goes
in no theory. Certainly, there is Christian theology (theo – logy). But
theology is only a rational projection of living religious experience.
In history, theology was a rational reaction on deviations in religious
life. Religious dogmata mark only the boundaries dividing the Truth from
delusion. But Truth itself one perceives superrationally, it is ontological… In
culture man creates never new being, he does only its symbols: painting,
musical piece, scientific or philosophical theories. Christianity in its kernel
is a life itself, a true life, where being and sense coincide; it is reducible
to no theory. This supreme life can be grasped only by faith as a highest
synthesis[7]
of human abilities and one perceives it more and more to the extent of theosis,
the graceful transfiguration of human nature by God’s energies…
So, we see two main opposite streams in
culture: upwords – from the unknown to knowledge, from darkness to light, from
man to God; and downwords – from God to man, from Heaven to Earth, maintaining
order and peace, giving light, commandments, faith and hope. It is their
fragile balance that culture consists of.
[1] See e.g. Galileo G. Discussions and
mathematical proves. V.1 Moscow, 1934 (in Russian).
[2] Firstly Leibniz gives his definition of function. See in my book: Katasonov
V.N. Metaphysical mathematics of XVII century. Moscow, 1994. Ch.I (in
Russian).
[3] Metaphizicheskie nachala estestvoznanija. P.58 // Kant I. Works
in 6 v., V.6. Moscow, 1966 (in Russian).
[4] See in my book: Katasonov V.N. He who
strove with the infinite. Philosophical and religious aspects of genesis of
G.Cantor’s set theory. Moscow, 1999. P.99-102 (in Russian).
[5] It is well known that by this way Kant put the question about God in his
philosophy of natural science. See: Kant I. Critics of pure reason.
Transcendental dialectics, Ideal of pure reason // Works in 6 v., V.3. Moscow,
1964. P.501 – 592 (in Russian).
[6] Pascal B. Thoughts. Sankt – Petersburg, P.106 – 110 (in
Russian). Compare with M. Heidegger’s: “Questioning is a piety of
thought” ( Question about technics. P.66 // Novaia tehnokraticheskaia volna na
Zapade. Moscow, 1986. P45-66 (in Russian)).
[7] Famous Russian theologian A.S.Khomiakov proposed his interpretation of
faith as a highest synthesis of reason’s abilities. See my paper: Katasonov
V.N. Idea of the integral reason in Russian philosophy and Russian Orthodox
Church // VII Christmas’ Readings. Moscow, 2000. P.97-118 (in Russian).